Wednesday, December 29, 2010

Retributive Theory

Retributive justification for state punishment of criminal activities emphasizes proportionality between the punishment and the crime being punished. There are three options for proportionality in a given case. There can be Equal Proportionality (EPro), Lesser Proportionality (LPro) and Greater Proportionality (GPro).

EPro is represented by 'an eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth'. If someone commits a criminal wrong against someone else, the punishment should be equal against the offender, sometimes taking the same form. It is intuitive and has the strength of an appeal to justice, balancing the scales.

LPro maintains that the punishment should be proportionate, but it denies that it needs to be the equal. This is sometimes justified by saying that a state's punishment is justified because it censures and condemns the offender, and it sends a message to the offender and others that the act is not tolerated. LPro theorists also sometimes argue that strictly equal punishments are barbaric. How is a government justified in doing to the offender what the offender did to others if it is an offensive act?

GPro is less popular than I think it should be. I do not know of a pure retributivist who advocates GPro. How would one justify the GPro position from a purely retributivist perspective? I think the general flow of the argument is pretty simple. A infringes on one of B's human rights without provocation, and this offence has a severity of 2, on a scale of 1-5. This is wrong; it is unacceptable. The state with jurisdiction should, after a fair trial resulting in a jury verdict and so forth, find a sentence with a severity of 2. However, it should sentence A to more than a level 2 punishment. This is due to its justified role in punishing such an offender. An equal-consequence response by the state to an offence would not be equal because the offender was not justified in his infringement on B's human rights but the state is justified in its punishment. Therefore, in order for it to be equal in all respects, the punishment must add to the equivalent-consequence sentence an addition for the unjustified violation of B's human rights. So, GPro can be justified if punishment is understood to be properly equal to unjustified crime.

6 comments:

  1. Where do you stand?

    Also, question on GPro... beyond numbers, can you give an example of how this would play out for something like armed robbery, or 1st degree murder, or even just a traffic violation?

    ReplyDelete
  2. GPro, baby. I don't really know what you mean. Rephrase it?

    ReplyDelete
  3. Whoa! The GPro of Exodus 22:1 is more severe than I thought: "If a man shall steal an ox, or a sheep, and kill it, or sell it; he shall restore five oxen for an ox, and four sheep for a sheep."

    Now that's a deterrent! You could never make a living as an ox-thief or even a sheep-thief with these odds. Perhaps the difference of 5:1 ox versus 4:1 sheep is due to the fact that oxen were worth more.

    ReplyDelete
  4. [Original post]: The OT contains examples of both EPro and GPro. An eye for an eye is the famous formulation of EPro, and the OT case law in Exodus requires five sheep repaid to the victim of four sheep stolen, as I recall, obviously as a deterrent to sheep-stealing. If EPro were applied, crime could pay as the profit comes from each incident when the thief is not caught. But GPro insures a loss for the thief when caught, making thievery less attractive.

    ReplyDelete
  5. We criminologists ;) are very sceptical about deterrence as a reason for criminal sentences. I was looking for a different one, one dependent on something besides influencing potential criminals. I think there is something in a human rights/justified versus unjustified action that could be further considered.

    ReplyDelete
  6. Your elevation of the inherent justice of a policy over pragmatic considerations is interesting and praiseworthy.

    ReplyDelete